DECLARATION ON PROFESSIONAL ETHICS
Adopted: August 1985
Background note
The involvement of the International Statistical Institute in establishing a declaration on professional ethics has extended over seven years. The Bureau of the Institute, in response to representations by members and a proposal by the Institute's Committee on Future Directions, established a Committee on a Code of Ethics for Statisticians, in 1979, during the 42nd ISI Session in Manila. The Committee worked to prepare a plenary meeting at the subsequent Buenos Aires Session in 1981 during which a consensus in favour of drawing up a code developed: the 'code' was to be prepared for acceptance by the Institute during its Centenary Celebration in 1985.
The Committee was composed of Roger Jowell (Chairman), W. Edwards Deming, Arno Donda, Helmut V. Muhsam and Edmund Rapaport, and it subsequently co-opted Edmundo Berumen-Torres, Gilbert Motsemme and Rene Padieu.
The Declaration which has emerged is the result of an extensive process of drafting and redrafting, of consultation with the entire ISI membership and with the ISI's Sections, of open meetings and written consultations which occurred between December 1981 and August 1985. The drafting of the Declaration provoked much interest and genuine debate which continued into the week before it was to be placed before the General Assembly of the Institute for adoption.
After due consideration and deliberation the General Assembly adopted the following resolution on 21 August 1985: 'The General Assembly of the International Statistical Institute,
1) recognising that the aim of the Declaration on Professional Ethics for Statisticians is to document shared professional values and experience as a means of providing guidance rather than regulation,
adopts the Declaration as an affirmation of the membership's concern with these matters and of its resolve to promote knowledge and interest in professional ethics among statisticians worldwide;
2) determines to send the Declaration to all members of the ISI and its Sections and to disseminate it, as appropriate, within the statistical profession;
3) commends the Committee responsible for developing the Declaration for its thorough, efficient and successful work during the last five years.'
In accordance with the spirit and letter of the resolution the International Statistical Institute is privileged to present to the reader the ISI Declaration on Professional Ethics with the hope and in the belief that this document will assist colleagues throughout the world in the pursuit of their professional goals and responsibilities.
Preamble
Statisticians work within a variety of economic, cultural, legal and political settings, each of which influences the emphasis and focus of statistical inquiry. They also work within one of several different branches of their discipline, each involving its own techniques and procedures and its own ethical approach. Many statisticians work in fields such as economics, psychology, sociology, medicine, whose practitioners have ethical conventions that may influence the conduct of statisticians in their fields. Even within the same setting and branch of statistics, individuals may have different moral precepts which guide their work. Thus, no declaration could successfully impose a rigid set of rules to which statisticians everywhere should be expected to adhere, and this document does not attempt to do so.
The aim of this declaration is to enable the statistician's individual ethical judgements and decisions to be informed by shared values and experience, rather than to be imposed by the profession. The declaration therefore seeks to document widely held principles of statistical inquiry and to identify the factors that obstruct their implementation. It is framed in the recognition that, on occasions, the operation of one principle will impede the operation of another, that statisticians - in common with other occupational groups - have competing obligations not all of which can be fulfilled simultaneously. Thus, implicit or explicit choices between principles will sometimes have to be made. The declaration does not attempt to resolve these choices or to allocate greater priority to one of its principles than to another. Instead it offers a framework within which the conscientious statistician should, for the most part, be able to work comfortably. Where departures from the framework of principles are contemplated, they should be the result of deliberation rather than of ignorance.
The declaration's first intention is thus to be informative and descriptive rather than authoritarian or prescriptive. Second, it is designed to be applicable as far as possible to different areas of statistical methodology and application. For this reason its provisions are fairly broadly drawn. Third, although the principles are framed so as to have wider application to decisions than to the issues it specifically mentions, the declaration is by no means exhaustive. It is designed in the knowledge that it will require periodic updating and amendment. Fourth, neither the principles nor the commentaries are concerned with general written or unwritten rules or norms such as compliance with the law or the need for probity. The declaration restricts itself as far as possible to matter of specific concern to statistical inquiry.
The text is divided into four section, each of which contains principles or sets of principles followed by short commentaries on the conflicts and difficulties inherent in their operation. The principles are interrelated and therefore need to be considered together; their order of presentation should not be taken as an order of precedence.
At the end of each section, as here, a short annotated bibliography is provided for those who wish to pursue the issues or to consult more detailed texts.
4.3 Modifications to informed consent
On occasions, technical or practical considerations inhibit the achievement of prior informed consent. In these cases, the subjects' interests should be safeguarded in other ways. For example:
(a) Respecting rights in observation studies. In observation studies, where behaviour patterns are recorded without the subject's knowledge, statisticians should take care not to infringe what may be referred to as the 'private space' of an individual or group. This will vary from culture to culture.
(b) Dealing with proxies. In cases where a 'proxy' is utilised to answer questions on behalf of a subject, say because access to the subject is uneconomic or because the subject is too ill or too young to participate directly, care should be taken not to infringe the 'private space' of the subject or to disturb the relationship between the subject and the proxy. Where indications exist or emerge that the subject would object to certain information being disclosed, such information should not be sought by proxy.
(c)Secondary use of records. In cases where a statistician has been granted access to, say, administrative or medical records or other research material for a new or supplementary inquiry, the custodian's permission to use the records should not relieve the statistician from having to consider the likely reactions, sensitivities and interests of the subjects concerned, including their entitlement to anonymity.
(d)Misleading potential subjects. In studies where the measurement objectives preclude the prior disclosure of material information to subjects, statisticians should weigh the likely consequences of any proposed deception. To withhold material information from, or to misinform, subjects involves a deceit, whether by omission or commission, temporarily or permanently, which will face legitimate censure unless it can be justified.
A serious problem arises for statisticians when methodological requirements conflict with the requirement of informed consent. Many cases exist in which the provision of background information to subjects (say, about the purpose or sponsorship of a study), or even the process of alerting them to the fact that they are subjects (as in observation studies), would be likely to produce a change or reaction that would defeat or interfere with the objective of the measurement. These difficulties may lead statisticians to waive informed consent and to adopt either covert measurement techniques or deliberate deception in the interests of accuracy.
The principles above urge extreme caution in these cases and advise statisticians to respect the imputed wishes of subjects. Thus, in observation studies or in studies involving proxies, the principle to be followed is that mere indications of reluctance on the part of an uninformed or unconsenting subject should be taken as a refusal to participate. Similarly, in the case of secondary use of records, statisticians should have regard to any obligations already owed to subjects. Any other course of action in these cases would be likely to demonstrate a lack of respect for the subject's interests and to undermine the relationship between statistician and subject.
Statistical inquiries involving deliberate deception of subjects (by omission or commission) are rare and extremely difficult to defend. Clear methodological advantages exist for deception in some psychological studies, for instance, where revealing the purpose would tend to bias the responses. But, as Diener and Crandall (1978) have argued 'science itself is built upon the value of truth'; thus deception by scientists will tend to destroy their credibility and standing (see Clause 3.1). If deception were widely practised in statistical inquiries, subjects would, in effect, be taught not to 'trust those who by social contract are deemed trustworthy and whom they need to trust' (Baumrind, 1972).
Nonetheless, it would be as unrealistic to outlaw deception in statistical inquiry as it would be to outlaw it in social interaction. Minor deception is employed in many forms of human contact (tact, flattery, etc.) and statisticians are no less likely than the rest of the population to be guilty of such practices. It remains the duty of statisticians and their collaborators, however, not to pursue methods of inquiry that are likely to infringe human values and sensibilities. To do so, whatever the methodological advantages, would be to endanger the reputation of statistics and the mutual trust between statisticians and society which is a prerequisite for much statistical work. (See Clause 3.1).
For these reasons, where informed consent cannot be acquired in advance, there is a case, where practicable, for seeking it post hoc, once the methodological advantage - of covert observation, of deception, or of withholding information - has been achieved.
References
* Ader, Gerard (1977). Confidentiality and business statistics in the European Communities. Eurostat; Paris.
* Agar, Michael H. (1980). The professional stranger: an informal introduction to ethnography. New York; Academic Press.
* AIS-Association des Administrateurs de l'Insee (1984). Code de deontologie statistique. Paris; AIS
* Akeroyd, Anne V. (1984). Ethics in relation to information, the profession and governments. In Ellen, Roy F., ed., Ethnographic research: a guide to general conduct. London; Academic Press. Research methods in social anthropology 1, 133-154.
* ASA-American Statistical Association (1980). Interim Code of Conduct-General Guidelines. Amstat News 69, 20-21.
* ASA-American Statistical Association (1983). Ethical Guidelines for statistical practice: historical perspective. Report of the ASA ad hoc committee on professional ethics; and Discussion. The American Statistician 37 (1): 1-19.
* Appell, George Nathan (1978). Ethical dilemmas in anthropological inquiry: a case book. Waltham, Mass.; Croassroads Press.
* BAAS-British Association for the Advancement of Science (1974). Does research threaten privacy or does privacy threaten research? Report of a study group. London; BAAS. Publication 74/1.
* Barnes, John Arundel (1980). Who should know what? Social science, privacy and ethics. Cambridge; Cambridge University Press.
* Barnes, John Arundel (1984). Ethical and political compromises in social research. Wisconsin sociologists 21, 100-111
* Barnett, Steven (1983). 'Never mind the quality ... will it give us the answers we want?' Social research Association News November: 1-2.
* Baumrind, Diana (1972). Reactions to the May 1972 draft report of the ad hoc committee on ethical standards in psychological research. American psychologist 27, 1083-1086.
* Beauchamp, Tom L. Faden, Ruth, R., Wallace, R. Jay & Walters, LeRoy (1982). Editors. Ethical issues in social science research. Baltimore; Johns Hopkins University Press.
* Bok, Sissela (1982). Secrets: on the ethics of concealment and revelation. New York; Pantheon books.
* Boruch, Robert Francis, & Cecil, Joe Shelby (1979). Assuring the confidentiality of social research data. Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press.
* Boruch, Robert Francis, & Cecil, Joe Shelby (1982). Statistical strategies for preserving privacy in direct inquiry. In Sieber 1982b: 207-232.
* Boruch, Robert Francis, & Cecil, Joe Shelby (1983). Solutions to ethical and legal problems in social research. New York; Academic Press.
* Bower, Robert Turrell, & De Gasparis, Priscilla (1978). Ethics in social research: protecting the interests of human subjects. New York; Praeger.
* Bryant, E.C. and Hansen, M.H. (1976). Invasion of privacy and surveys, a growing dilemma. In: H.W. Sinaiko and L.A. Broadling, eds. Perspectives on attitude assessment; surveys and their alternatives. Champaign; Illinois Free Press.
* Bulmer, Martin (1979). Editor. Censuses, surveys and privacy. London; Macmillan.
* Bulmer, Martin (1982). Editor. Social research ethics: an examination of the merits of covert participant observation. London; Macmillan.
* Burgess, Robert G. (1984). In the field: an introduction to field research. London; Allen & Unwin. Contemporary social research 8. Canada Council (1977). Consultative group on ethics. Ethics: report of the consultative group on ethics. Ottawa; Canada Council.
* Capron, Alexander Morgan (1982). Is consent always necessary in social science research? In Beauchamp et al. 1982: 215-231.
* Carroll, James D., & Kneer, Charles R. (1976). The APSA confidentiality in social science research project: a final report. PS. 9: 416-419.
* Cassell, Joan (1982a). Does risk-benefit analysis apply to moral evaluation of social research? In Beauchamp et al. 1982: 144-162.
* Cassell, Joan (1982b). Harms, benefits, wrongs, and rights in fieldwork. In Sieber 1982a: 7-31.
* Chakravarty, S. (1985). Use of statistics for planning in the economic and related sectors with emphasis on macro-level planning - review of Indian experience. Paper presented at 45th Session of ISI, Amsterdam.
* Crispo, John Herbert Gillespie (1975). The public right to know: accountability in the secretive society. Toronto; McGraw-Hill Ryerson.
* Dalenius, T. (1979). Data protection legislation in Sweden: a statistician's perspective. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society A, 142 (3): 285-298.
* Dalenius, T. (1983). Informed consent or RSVP. In: W.G. Madow, H. Nisselsen and I. Olkin, eds. Incomplete data in sample surveys, Vol. 3: 85-106. New York; Academic Press.
* Deming, W. Edwards (1965). Principles of professional statistical practice. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics. Vol. 36 No. 4: 1883-1900.
* Deming, W. Edwards (1982). Code of professional conduct: a personal view. International Statistical Review 40, 214-219.
* Diener, Edward, & Crandall, Rick (1978). Ethics in social and behavioural research. Chicago; University of Chicago Press.
* Douglas, Jack Daniel (1979). Living morality versus bureaucratic fiat. In Klockars & O'Connor 1979: 13-33.
* Durbin, J. (1979). Statistics and the Report of the Data Protection Committee. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society A, 142 (3): 299-316.
* Finney, D.J. (1984). Comment in Proceedings of the 44th Session of the ISI Volume L Book 3: 553.
* Flaherty, David H. (1979). Privacy and government data banks: an international perspective. London; Mansell.
* Flaherty, David H., Hanis, Edward H., & Mitchell, S. Paula (1979). Privacy and access to government data for research: an international bibliography. London; Mansell.
* Form, William Humbert (1973). Field problems in comparative research: the politics of distrust. In Armer, Michael, & Grimshaw, Allan Day, eds., Comparative social research: methodology problems and strategies: 83-117. New York; Wiley.
* Frankel, L. (1976). Statistics and Peoples - the Statistician's Responsibilities. Journal of American Statistical Association 70 (353): 9-16.
* Freidson, Eliot (1978). Comment on Stephenson, M., et al., articles on ethics. American sociologist 13, 159- 160.
* Freund, Paul E. (1969). Editor. Ethical aspects of experimentation with human subjects. Daedalus 98 (2), xiv, 219-597.
* Geller, Daniel M. (1982). Alternatives to deception: why, what, and how? In Sieber 1982b: 39-55.
* Gonzales, M.E., Ogus, J.L., Shapiro, G. & Tepping, B.J. (1975). Standards for discussion and presentation of errors in surveys and census data. Journal of American Statistical Association 70 (351) II: 5-23.
* GSS-Government Statistical Service (1984). Code of practice on the handling of data obtained from statistical inquiries. London; HMSO.
* Hansen, M.H. (1983). Discussion on Dalenius, T. (1983). In W.G. Madow, H. Nisselson and I. Olkin eds. Incomplete Data in Sample Surveys, vol. 3: 125-127. New York; Academic Press.
* Hartley, Shirley Foster (1982). Sampling strategies and the threat to privacy. In Sieber 1982b; 186-189.
* Jahoda, Marie (1981). To publish or not to publish? Journal of social issues 37, 208-220.
* Johnson, Carole Gaar (1982). Risks in the publication of fieldwork. In Sieber 1982a: 71-91.
* Jowell, Roger (1979). Informed consent in survey research. Bulletin of the International Statistical Institute, (Proceedings of the 42nd session) 66, 273-276.
* Jowell, Roger (1981). A professional code for statisticians? Some ethical and technical conflicts. Bulletin of the International Statistical Institute (Proceedings of the 43rd session) 49 (1), 165-209.
* Klaw, Spencer (1970). The Faustian bargain. In Brown, Martin, ed., The social responsibility of the scientist. New York Free Press: 3-15.
* Klockars, Carl B. (1979). Dirty hands and deviant subjects. In Klockars & O'Connor 1979: 261-282.
* Klockars, Carl B., & O'Connor, Finbarr W. (1979). Editors. Deviance and decency: the ethics of research with human subjects. Beverly Hills; Sage. Sage annual review of studies in deviance 3.
* Levine, Robert J. (1978). The role of assessment of risk-benefit criteria in the determination of the appropriateness of research involving human subjects. In United States. National Commission for the protection of human subjects of biomedical and behavioural research. Appendix. The Belmont report: government printing office. DHEW publication (OS) 78-0013.
* Levine, Robert J. (1979). Clarifying the concepts of research ethics. Hastings Centre report 9 (3): 21-26.
* Loo, Chalsa M. (1982). Vulnerable populations: case studies in crowding research. In Sieber 1982b: 105-126.
* Michael, James (1982). Privacy. In Wallington, Peter, ed., Civil liberties 1984. London; Martin Robertson: 131-150.
* Mirvis, Philip H., & Seashore, Stanley E. (1982). Creating ethical relationships in organisational research. In Sieber 1982b: 79-104.
* Muhsam, Helmut (1985). On two human rights involved in the ISI Declaration on Professional Ethics. Contributed paper, Proceedings of the 45th Session.
* Nyitrai, V. (1985). The socio-economic statistical information system as a useful means for planning. Paper presented at 45th Session of ISI, Amsterdam.
* O'Connor, Michael Edward (1976). Prison research: a methodological commentary on being a known observer. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology 9, 227-234.
* O'Connor, Michael Edward, & Barnes, John Arundel (1983). Bulmer on pseudo-patient studies: a critique. Sociological review n.s. 31, 753-758.
* Okely, Judith (1984). Fieldwork in the home counties. Royal Anthropological Institute News 61, 4-6.
* Pool, Ithiel de Sola (1979). Protecting human subjects of research: an analysis on proposed amendments to HEW policy. PS 12, 452-455.
* Pool, Ithiel de Sola (1980). Response by Pool. PS 13, 203-204
* Powell, John P. (1983). Professional ethics in academia. Vestes 27 (2), 29-32.
* Reeves, Tom Kynaston, & Harper, Donald George (1981). Surveys at work: a practitioner's guide. London; McGraw-Hill.
* Reynolds, Paul Davidson (1975). Value dilemmas in the professional conduct of social science. International social science journal 27, 563-611.
* Reynolds, Paul Davidson (1979). Ethical dilemmas and social science research: an analysis of moral issues confronting investigators in research using human participants. San Francisco; Jossey-Bass.
* Reynolds, Paul Davidson (1982). Ethics and social science research. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.; Prentice-Hall.
* Rynkiewich, Michael Allen, & Spradley, James Phillip (1976). Editors. Ethics and anthropology: dilemmas in fieldwork. New York; Wiley.
* Ryten, Jacob (1983). Some general consideration as a result of an Ecuadorian case study. Bulletin of the International Statistical Institute (Proceedings of the 43rd Session) 49 (2), 639-665.
* Schuler, Heinz (1982). Ethical problems in psychological research. New York; Academic Press.
* SCPR-Social and Community Planning Research Working Party (1974). Survey research and privacy: report of a working party. London; Social and Community Planning Research.
* Shils, Edward (1967). Privacy and power. In Pool, Ithiel de Sola, ed., Contemporary political science: toward empirical theory. New York; McGraw-Hill: 228-276.
* Sieber, Joan E. (1982a). Editor. The ethics of social research: fieldwork, regulation, and publication. New York; Springer.
* Sieber, Joan E. (1982b). Editor. The ethics of social research: surveys and experiments. New York; Springer. Simmel, Georg (1908). Soziologie. Untersuchungen ueber die Formen der Vergesellschaftung. Leipzig; Duncker & Humblot.
* Simmel, Georg (1952). The sociology of Georg Simmel. Editor. Wolfe, Kurt Heinrich. Glencoe; Illinois Free Press.
* Singer, Eleanor (1978). Informed consent: consequences for response rate and response quality for social surveys. American sociological review 43, 144-162.
* Sjoberg, Gideon (1967). Editor. Ethics, politics, and social research. Cambridge, Mass.; Schenkman.
* Stocking, S. Holly, & Dunwoody, Sharon L. (1982). Social science in the mass media: images and evidence. In Sieber 1982a: 151-169.
* Swiss Academy of Science. Ethical Guidelines for Animal Experimentation.
* Tefft, Stanton K. (1980). Editor. Secrecy: a cross-cultural perspective. New York; Human Sciences Press.
* Warwick, Donald P. (1983). The politics and ethics of field research. In Bulmer, Martin, & Warwick, Donald P., eds. Social research in developing countries: surveys and censuses in the Third World. Chichester; Wiley, 315-330.
* Wax, Murray L. (1980). Paradoxes of 'consent' to the practice of fieldwork. Social problems 27, 272-283.
* Wax, Murray L. (1982). Research reciprocity rather than informed consent in fieldwork. In Sieber 1982a, 33- 48.
* Wax, Murray L., & Cassell, Joan (1981). From regulation to reflection: ethics in social research. American sociologist 16, 224-229.
* Webb, Eugene John, and others (1966). Unobtrusive measures: nonreactive research in the social sciences. Chicago; Rand McNally.
* Williams, K. (1985). Use of statistical information for assessing social conditions and monitoring and evaluation of development programmes - experience of African countries. Paper presented at 45th Session of ISI, Amsterdam.
* World Medical Association Declaration of Helsinki (1964). Revised 1975. Reprinted in Duncan, H.S., Dunstan, G.R. and Welbourn, R.B. eds. (1981 Dictionary of Medical Ethics. Revised and enlarged version, Darton, Longham and Todd, London).